Accountability for reasonableness

问责 政治学 法律与经济学 法学 社会学
作者
Norman Daniels
出处
期刊:BMJ [BMJ]
卷期号:321 (7272): 1300-1301 被引量:653
标识
DOI:10.1136/bmj.321.7272.1300
摘要

All health systems struggle with the issue of meeting population health needs fairly under resource constraints. Decisions about the implementation of new technologies provide a useful window into the larger issue, and a paper in this week's journal provides a valuable insight into the elements of decision making that decision makers themselves think important in trying to reach fair decisions on applying new technologies in health care.1 In mixed systems, like that in the United States, decisions whether to fund new technologies—drugs, devices, procedures—are made both by public agencies, such as the Health Care Financing Administration or the Veterans Administration, and by private indemnity insurers and managed care organisations. In the universal coverage systems of most developed countries such decisions are made by public agencies or authorities. Distrust has grown in all these settings.2,3 Clinicians, patients, and the public—propelled by the media, the internet, and direct to consumer advertising—often believe these decisions are guided solely by the “bottom line,” not patient welfare. The moral legitimacy of limits and priorities thus involves not just who has moral authority to set them, but how they are set. Some countries with universal coverage systems initially tried to address this problem of legitimacy by setting up national commissions to articulate principles that should govern the setting of priorities. Holm has argued that these principles proved too general and too unclear in practice.4 More generally, we probably lack consensus on principles capable of resolving disputes about rationing.5 A second wave of efforts to address priority setting has thus focused on developing fair, publicly acceptable processes for making these decisions. In the United States an active consumer movement has also focused on a patients' bill of rights as a vehicle for fair process. In the United Kingdom, awareness of the need for clear process is reflected in the establishment of the National Institute for Clinical Excellence (NICE) to handle some aspects of rationing.6,7 In pluralist societies we are likely to find reasonable disagreement about principles that should govern priority setting. For example, some will want to give more priority to the worst off, some less; some will be willing to aggregate benefits in ways that others are not. In the absence of consensus on principles, a fair process allows us to agree on what is legitimate and fair. Key elements of fair process will involve transparency about the grounds for decisions; appeals to rationales that all can accept as relevant to meeting health needs fairly; and procedures for revising decisions in light of challenges to them.8 Together these elements assure “accountability for reasonableness.”9 Fair procedures must also be empirically feasible. They must involve practices that can be sustained and that connect well with the goals of various stakeholders in the many institutional settings where these decisions are made. The value of the study by Singer et al in this issue is that it points to key elements of actual decision making processes that can be further improved to achieve legitimacy and fairness (p 1316).1 An ethical approach to fair process must build on their findings. A fair process requires publicity about the reasons and rationales that play a part in decisions. There must be no secrets where justice is involved, for people should not be expected to accept decisions that affect their well being unless they are aware of the grounds for those decisions. The study found that transparency was important to participants in the decisions, though it did not state whether the rationales for decisions were then made transparent to all affected by them. This broader transparency is a hallmark of fair process. Fair process also involves constraints on reasons. Fair minded people—those who seek mutually justifiable grounds for cooperation—must agree that the reasons, evidence, and rationales are relevant to meeting population health needs fairly, the shared goal of deliberation. The kinds of reasons described in the study meet this condition, but the institutions studied—committees concerned with implementing new technologies—did not face the more difficult task of comparing quite different benefits across different groups of patients under budget limits. Fair process also requires opportunities to challenge and revise decisions in light of the kinds of considerations all stakeholders may raise. Though the committees studied by Singer et al gave evidence that decisions improved—that is, became more sensitive to patient variations—through revision, there should be a mechanism for appeals to decisions by those affected by them. The fact that a single lay member of the cardiac committee did not function as effectively as the three lay members of the cancer committee is a lesson that must be taken seriously in designing fair procedures. Accountability for reasonableness makes it possible to educate all stakeholders about the substance of deliberation about fair decisions under resource constraints. It facilitates social learning about limits. It connects decision making in healthcare institutions to broader, more fundamental democratic deliberative processes. Accountability for reasonableness also occupies a middle ground in the debate between those calling for “explicit” and “implicit” rationing.10 Like implicit approaches, it does not require that principles for rationing be made explicit ahead of time. But, like explicit approaches, it does call for transparency about reasoning that all can eventually agree is relevant. Since we may not be able to construct principles that yield fair decisions ahead of time, we need a process that allows us to develop those reasons over time as we face real cases. The social learning that this approach facilitates provides our best prospect of achieving agreement over sharing medical resources fairly.

科研通智能强力驱动
Strongly Powered by AbleSci AI

祝大家在新的一年里科研腾飞
科研通是完全免费的文献互助平台,具备全网最快的应助速度,最高的求助完成率。 对每一个文献求助,科研通都将尽心尽力,给求助人一个满意的交代。
实时播报
Sky36001完成签到,获得积分10
1秒前
Murphy~完成签到,获得积分10
2秒前
王二完成签到,获得积分10
4秒前
Sky36001发布了新的文献求助20
4秒前
shuai发布了新的文献求助10
5秒前
郑洋完成签到 ,获得积分10
8秒前
8秒前
XYT完成签到,获得积分10
10秒前
mito完成签到,获得积分10
10秒前
lhl完成签到,获得积分10
10秒前
时尚雨兰完成签到,获得积分10
12秒前
12秒前
mange完成签到 ,获得积分10
13秒前
天玄一刀完成签到,获得积分10
15秒前
zzzyyyuuu完成签到 ,获得积分10
16秒前
健壮的鸽子完成签到,获得积分10
20秒前
吴大语完成签到,获得积分10
20秒前
xiaxiao应助科研通管家采纳,获得100
23秒前
南风应助科研通管家采纳,获得10
23秒前
南风应助科研通管家采纳,获得10
23秒前
脑洞疼应助科研通管家采纳,获得10
23秒前
xiaxiao应助科研通管家采纳,获得100
23秒前
Curry发布了新的文献求助10
25秒前
文龙完成签到 ,获得积分10
26秒前
马香芦完成签到,获得积分10
28秒前
韦远侵完成签到 ,获得积分10
29秒前
tt完成签到,获得积分20
31秒前
ccl完成签到,获得积分10
32秒前
方又亦完成签到,获得积分10
34秒前
星辰大海应助周周采纳,获得10
35秒前
lovekobe完成签到,获得积分20
36秒前
LM完成签到,获得积分10
36秒前
zero完成签到,获得积分10
36秒前
LY发布了新的文献求助20
37秒前
37秒前
巴山郎完成签到,获得积分10
38秒前
曾经小伙完成签到 ,获得积分10
39秒前
Man_proposes完成签到,获得积分10
40秒前
lxlcx完成签到,获得积分10
40秒前
42秒前
高分求助中
Востребованный временем 2500
The Three Stars Each: The Astrolabes and Related Texts 1500
Classics in Total Synthesis IV: New Targets, Strategies, Methods 1000
Les Mantodea de Guyane 800
Mantids of the euro-mediterranean area 700
The Oxford Handbook of Educational Psychology 600
有EBL数据库的大佬进 Matrix Mathematics 500
热门求助领域 (近24小时)
化学 医学 生物 材料科学 工程类 有机化学 生物化学 内科学 物理 纳米技术 计算机科学 遗传学 化学工程 基因 复合材料 免疫学 物理化学 细胞生物学 催化作用 病理
热门帖子
关注 科研通微信公众号,转发送积分 3413469
求助须知:如何正确求助?哪些是违规求助? 3015836
关于积分的说明 8871935
捐赠科研通 2703538
什么是DOI,文献DOI怎么找? 1482357
科研通“疑难数据库(出版商)”最低求助积分说明 685250
邀请新用户注册赠送积分活动 679970