Self-knowledge and reflection in Schopenhauer’s view of agency

代理(哲学) 认识论 建设性的 美德 性格(数学) 动作(物理) 哲学 社会学 心理学 计算机科学 数学 物理 几何学 过程(计算) 量子力学 操作系统
作者
Sean T. Murphy
出处
期刊:Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy [Taylor & Francis]
卷期号:: 1-27
标识
DOI:10.1080/0020174x.2023.2178029
摘要

ABSTRACTThis paper examines the roles that self-knowledge and reflection play in Schopenhauer’s view of agency. Focusing in particular on the discussion of the acquired character, his cognitive theory of motivation, and the idea of intellectual freedom, I argue that we find two conceptions of rational agency in Schopenhauer. The ‘minimal’ conception sees rational agency primarily as a kind of reflective motivation, whereas the ‘maximal’ or ‘robust’ conception sees rational agency as involving a kind of reflective self-organization. Furthermore, I argue that rational self-organization and acquired character go hand-in-hand: it is only in virtue of achieving the latter that one achieves the former. Although some worry that the discussion of acquired character does not sit well with Schopenhauer’s broader determinist theory of action, the reading offered here aims to demonstrate that the two are reconcilable.KEYWORDS: Schopenhaueragencyactioncharacterself-knowledge‌reflection AcknowledgementsThank you to three anonymous referees for their constructive comments on an earlier version of this paper. I would also like to thank Sandra Shapshay, Allen Wood, and Ivan Verano for commenting on an even earlier draft of this paper.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1 Bratman Citation2007, 21.2 Worries along these lines have been around awhile and are discussed in: Patrick Gardiner Citation1963; Julian Young Citation1987; John E. Atwell Citation1990; David E. Cooper Citation1998; Bernard Reginster Citation2006; and Christopher Janaway Citation2012.3 Cooper Citation1998, 209.4 For recent work suggesting that Schopenhauer can make room for genuine reflective agency, but which also wishes to reject reading him as a ‘hard determinist’, opting instead for a ‘Kantian compatibilism’, see Shapshay Citation2017 and Citation2019. For another interesting discussion of Schopenhauer’s view of freedom see Zöller Citation2017.5 I wish to be noncommittal about whether this is best read as a psychological, metaphysical, or ontological thesis.6 Although he does believe that ‘higher animals’ exhibit a ‘semblance’ of individuality (W 1, 156). Here, we might think Schopenhauer has in mind, for examples, animals like elephants, about whom he often speaks highly, or his cherished poodles.7 This point holds regardless of the fact that Schopenhauer will of course grant that we do not always act rationally, and, indeed, that it is partially a good thing that we do not.8 According to Atwell, who makes a similar set of points, if we are to be identified with our individual character, then talk of creating or choosing our character suggests we would exist either characterless before this creation happened (but then we’d be effectively nothing) or we’d have to exist as someone else (odd). See Atwell Citation1990, 47. Shapshay also discusses this particular move with respect to Schopenhauer’s idea that character is inborn. See Shapshay Citation2017, 85.9 As we’ll see shortly, it could be expressing my species character, rather than my individual character. Still, Schopenhauer seems committed to needing some character facts in all explanations of things that happen in the empirical world.10 They need not always take this form, however. Schopenhauer grants that human motives can be perceptual/intuitive as well as rational/abstract. For example, in his discussion of the compassionate person, he states that for them to be moved to alleviate another’s suffering ‘no abstract cognition was required, but only intuitive cognition, the simple grasp of the concrete case, to which compassion responds at once without further mediation of thought’ (E, 232). Considering, however, the way Schopenhauer sometimes seems to want to divorce reason and virtue, we might wonder whether we should call compassionate motivation human motivation at all, given that it seems to draw less on our rational nature and more on our animal-volitional nature (see e.g. W 1, 312).11 I discuss and defend Schopenhauer's intellectualist handling of motivation in my 2022.12 For a careful treatment of the many dimensions of Schopenhauer’s concept of motivation see e.g. Janaway Citation1989 and Murphy Citation2022.13 For a discussion of Schopenhauer’s ‘expressivism’ about action see Schroeder Citation202014 Young Citation1987, 61. As I said, Young is optimistic about the prospects of giving an account of Schopenhauer’s view of agency that allows space for the acquired character without rendering it full of inconsistencies. I use Young’s statement of the worry, however, because I think it speaks to an intuitive understanding of the tension, though not the right one. For other sympathetic takes on the acquired character see Wicks Citation2008; Koßler Citation2016; and Shapshay Citation2019.15 See e.g. Young Citation1987, 57-8.16 The kind of self-knowledge at issue here is not merely the kind of immediate knowledge we might expect rational agents to have of the contents of their mental states. Instead, what Schopenhauer has in mind is what some today call ‘Socratic self-knowledge.’ To echo Ursula Renz, this is self-knowledge thought of as a ‘personal achievement’; it is not the simple self-knowledge that comes about as a matter of simple reflective success, which is something that most agents enjoy, and therefore hardly constitutes an achievement. See Renz Citation2017. It is a further interesting question how the valuable kind of self-knowledge discussed here relates to that other kind of valuable self-knowledge in Schopenhauer, namely the sort had by the agent who is on her way to self-resignation. For a discussion of self-knowledge in this context, see Bernard Reginster Citation2017.17 Young Citation1987, 57.18 Janaway Citation2002, 67.19 Cooper Citation1998, 214; my emphasis.20 Ibid.21 The implication here being that Atwell does not find responsible agency to be incompatible with practical essentialism. For Atwell’s careful argument to this effect, see Atwell Citation1990, 43-39.22 Atwell Citation1990, 134.23 Ibid, 135.24 It strikes me that Schopenhauer is more interested in wavering agency than he is in a wavering character, but at this point this difference isn’t important.25 It is central to Schopenhauer’s discussion of acquired character that part of the reason why it is good for us to get to know ourselves, and then act accordingly, is so that we may avoid feelings of self-dissatisfaction (W 1, 333). I’ll say more about this later.26 Atwell Citation1990, 64.27 A possible way to avoid the issue is to appeal to the discussion of the intelligible character in hopes of grounding something like empirical freedom in this world. Shapshay makes a move like this. For Shapshay, commentators move too quickly when they identify the intelligible character with the will as thing in itself; rather, she says it ‘is something metaphysically intermediate between the world of representation and the thing in itself: It is a special Idea, which is itself an objectivation of a particular act of the metaphysical will’ (Shapshay Citation2017, 94). If the intelligible character mediates between these two ‘worlds’, then it becomes possible to explain empirical agency on its basis.28 Translation amended.29 Dale Jacquette takes the artificiality, or what he calls the ‘superficiality’ of acquired character to indicate that it cannot be central to Schopenhauer’s accounts of character and agency. See Jacquette Citation2005, 201.30 Bratman Citation2007, 195-196.31 Bratman Citation2007, 91.32 To be sure, he also speaks about ‘contaminations of cognition by individuality’ (P 2, 62). Thus, it’s not just that cognition contaminates individuality, as we see in the passage from the main work quoted here. The contamination is mutual.33 Now this doesn’t mean that I can do everything a human being can do; at least, it doesn’t mean that I can do it successfully. Each of us is just one human being, just one member of the human species. It also doesn’t mean that I should want to do whatever a human being can do.34 This is an idea we find in Atwell Citation1990.35 Again, we know this to be an exaggeration, give that compassionate actions are motivated by intuitive, rather than abstract cognitions.36 Interestingly, what Norman et. al. translate as ‘self-restraint’ is the German word Selbstüberwindung, which might also be translated as ‘self-overcoming’. Needless to say, this makes it worth exploring in more detail the extent to which Schopenhauer’s discussion of acquired character, no matter how disguised, lies behind Nietzsche’s view of mature agency.37 There is an interesting parallel to draw here between the form of agency Schopenhauer says is constitutive of acquired character and what Bratman’s planning theory, although a full working out of the connections, and the degree to which Schopenhauer might be read as a planning theorist is beyond the scope of this paper.38 See W 1, 322.39 Schopenhauer says that our capacity for reflective decision is what ‘conditions the possibility of expression of the individual character’ (W 1, 327). He also notes that desires only express our species character, not our individual character, meaning: our individuality rests not just on our wants, but on how we think about them, and the form of expression we give to them (W 1, 326).40 ‘But given the groundlessness of the will itself, people have at the same time overlooked the necessity that governs it wherever it appears, and declared deeds to be free when they were not, since every individual action follows with strict necessity from the effect of a motive on the character’ (W 1, 138; my emphasis).41 To make the language of motives ‘reaching’ character through cognition less murky, consider an example. If I am generally courageous, yet I don’t know that the child before me in the lake is drowning, but instead think they’re waving their arms and having fun, then I am not likely to jump in. And part of the explanation why will be because I misrecognized (mis-cognized) the situation, which caused the true motives before me not to reach my character. At the same time, I could recognize the situation aright and not be a courageous person: I could be a coward. In that case, the motives also won’t reach my character, but not because of a problem of cognition. But in both cases, we see that in many cases (but not all), motives need to reach character (via cognition) for them to get a grip on the agent.42 Furthermore, while Schopenhauer does limit his discussion of obstacles to intellectual freedom to cases of pathology, there doesn’t seem to be any special reason why it cannot be extended to less pathological cases as well. For example, simple instances of self-deception and self-ignorance.43 See several of the essays in Bratman Citation2007 for a working out of the details of this theory.44 Motives cause actions: so, if I am acting out of character, then that typically will mean I’m also being moved in a way that is not in keeping with my character45 Atwell Citation1990, 63.46 There’s no problem with this, since for Schopenhauer we are each of us a mix of the three fundamental incentives to action: egoism, compassion, and malice. See E, 238.47 Thanks to an anonymous referee for helping me to be clearer on this point.48 It is probably right to say that we should opt for a set of neutral or middle-ground epistemic states of self-relation as well; for example, states like ‘having a defeasible idea about my individual character’. Indeed, given the challenges of acquiring accurate self-knowledge, Schopenhauer is likely to say that this is the way most of us epistemically relate to ourselves.49 Recall the concluding element of the long passage quoted earlier: ‘Consequently to expect that a human being in the presence of the same occasion would act one way at one time but quite differently another time, would be as if one expected the same tree that bore cherries this summer to bear pears in the next (E, 76-7)’.

科研通智能强力驱动
Strongly Powered by AbleSci AI
更新
PDF的下载单位、IP信息已删除 (2025-6-4)

科研通是完全免费的文献互助平台,具备全网最快的应助速度,最高的求助完成率。 对每一个文献求助,科研通都将尽心尽力,给求助人一个满意的交代。
实时播报
HJX发布了新的文献求助10
刚刚
刚刚
animenz完成签到,获得积分10
1秒前
去玩儿发布了新的文献求助10
1秒前
完美世界应助星辉采纳,获得10
1秒前
科研发布了新的文献求助10
2秒前
longlulu完成签到,获得积分20
3秒前
4秒前
哈密瓜完成签到,获得积分10
4秒前
琦琦完成签到,获得积分10
5秒前
宿帅帅完成签到,获得积分10
5秒前
SYLH应助韩jl采纳,获得10
6秒前
CR7应助韩jl采纳,获得20
6秒前
6秒前
Gj完成签到,获得积分10
7秒前
Cary发布了新的文献求助10
7秒前
8秒前
8秒前
8秒前
Dr.lee发布了新的文献求助10
11秒前
11秒前
welldone发布了新的文献求助10
12秒前
12秒前
Keng发布了新的文献求助30
12秒前
星辉给星辉的求助进行了留言
13秒前
快乐完成签到,获得积分10
14秒前
15秒前
热心的飞兰完成签到,获得积分20
15秒前
阳光下的味道完成签到,获得积分10
15秒前
16秒前
隐形曼青应助SOS采纳,获得10
16秒前
18秒前
18秒前
li发布了新的文献求助10
18秒前
zyy发布了新的文献求助10
18秒前
研友_VZG7GZ应助DrZheng采纳,获得10
19秒前
19秒前
19秒前
NexusExplorer应助DD采纳,获得10
19秒前
万能图书馆应助xiang采纳,获得10
20秒前
高分求助中
Ophthalmic Equipment Market by Devices(surgical: vitreorentinal,IOLs,OVDs,contact lens,RGP lens,backflush,diagnostic&monitoring:OCT,actorefractor,keratometer,tonometer,ophthalmoscpe,OVD), End User,Buying Criteria-Global Forecast to2029 2000
A new approach to the extrapolation of accelerated life test data 1000
Cognitive Neuroscience: The Biology of the Mind (Sixth Edition) 1000
ACSM’s Guidelines for Exercise Testing and Prescription, 12th edition 588
Christian Women in Chinese Society: The Anglican Story 500
A Preliminary Study on Correlation Between Independent Components of Facial Thermal Images and Subjective Assessment of Chronic Stress 500
Technical Brochure TB 814: LPIT applications in HV gas insulated switchgear 500
热门求助领域 (近24小时)
化学 材料科学 医学 生物 工程类 有机化学 生物化学 物理 内科学 纳米技术 计算机科学 化学工程 复合材料 遗传学 基因 物理化学 催化作用 冶金 细胞生物学 免疫学
热门帖子
关注 科研通微信公众号,转发送积分 3960556
求助须知:如何正确求助?哪些是违规求助? 3506870
关于积分的说明 11132558
捐赠科研通 3239151
什么是DOI,文献DOI怎么找? 1790050
邀请新用户注册赠送积分活动 872129
科研通“疑难数据库(出版商)”最低求助积分说明 803128