摘要
The theory and practice of multiculturalism, of which multicultural and antiracist
education form a central part, currently faces opposition on two key fronts. The
first constitutes an alliance of conservative and some liberal commentators
whose principal aim is to defend orthodox liberalism against a politics of
difference represented by multiculturalism (see, for example, Bullivant, 1981;
Hughes, 1993; Ravitch, 1992; Schlesinger, 1991, 1992). Building on a post
second world war consensus of orthodox liberalism in social and political theory
(see Claude, 1955; Glazer, 1975; Porter, 1965, 1975), these commentators argue
that only the current organization of nation-states-represented most clearly by
the neutrality of the civic realm-can ensure personal autonomy, equality, and
common citizenship (at least in theory). In contrast, they argue that the politics
of multiculturalism-which they equate directly with the increasing public
recognition of various minority ethnic, cultural and/or religious identities-is
inherently destabilizing and destructive of the common bonds of nationhood. In
their view, multiculturalism is an approach which replaces universalism with
particularism and which introduces ethnicity unnecessarily and unhelpfully into
the civic realm-that is, ‘civil society’ in Gramsci’s (1971) sense of the term.1Indeed, at their most apocalyptic, these critics suggest that the accommodation of
multiculturalism may result in the immolation and/or ‘balkanization’ of
previously quiescent, harmonious nation-states. And all because the ‘cult of
ethnicity’, to use Schlesinger’s (1992) pejorative phrase, unnecessarily hardens
ethnic group boundaries; bringing difference and division where once was unity
and common purpose. The spectres of Rwanda and the former Yugoslavia
provide convenient and seemingly salutary examples here of where
multiculturalism might eventually take us.